Appendix D0 

The Ontological 'Kind' of Truth  and the Suppression of Knowing

I. Suppressing Kind, Denying Truth

This appendix emerges not from abstract theorizing, but from a direct confrontation with a recurring failure in modern and even theological thought: the failure to treat truth as an ontological kind (category). It addresses not only how this suppression occurs, but why it is not a mere oversight—it is logically indefensible, intellectually dishonest, and morally evasive.

At the heart of this problem is referential destabilization. Before a thing can be evaluated—morally, logically, or semantically—it must be ontologically stabilized as a kind. This is true for trees, persons, laws—and truth itself. If truth is treated as a shifting function, a linguistic projection, or a social construct, then it cannot be evaluated as truth. Judgment presupposes referential clarity. To deny kindhood is to preempt judgment through semantic sabotage.

I.A. The Foundational Pillar: Truth is a Kind

If we grant that reality is composed of kinds—tangible and intangible—then truth, like number, causality, and relation, must be classified among the intangible ontological kinds. It is not reducible to syntax, function, or perception.  One cannot coherently affirm a structured reality and yet deny truth’s reality. To know anything at all is to presuppose the reality of truth.  Thus, to deny truth as a kind is not only to evade being—it is to destroy the foundation of knowing itself.

I.B. Why This Is Not Just Moral Evasion

While moral evasion is indeed central (cf. Romans 1:18), it is not sufficient to explain the breadth of the suppression. The denial of truth as a kind is also:

I.B.1. Logically Fallacious

  • Category Error: Misclassifies truth as a social construct or linguistic product, when it is in fact a universal kind.
  • Performative Contradiction: The claim “truth is not real” presupposes truth to be valid.
  • Special Pleading: Applies logic, structure, and judgment in every domain—except where truth exposes moral obligation.

I.B.2. Intellectually Dishonest

  • Secular and academic systems continue to act as if truth is real (arguing, evaluating, publishing), while denying its ontological grounding.
  • The denial is often conscious, especially in post-structuralist and postmodern systems, where language is wielded as a tool of obfuscation, not illumination.

This is not innocent error—it is a simulated intellectual ecosystem, built on suppressed acknowledgment.

I.C. Why This Is Rarely Foregrounded

This suppression has gone largely unstated in mainstream discourse—even by systems that gesture toward it. This is partly due to:

  • Epistemic pluralism: a refusal to assert ontological hierarchies.
  • Deference to user autonomy (in interpretive traditions): reluctance to declare any confrontation absolute.
  • Fear of theological commitment: truth as ontological kind leads inevitably to God, and not an impersonal ground—but a personal, moral, self-disclosing Being.

This is why most modern systems orbit the issue without naming it.

Even theological models often fail here—preferring propositional or systematic truth over ontologically instantiated truth, as found in the person of Christ.

I.D. The Role of the Relational-Ontological Framework

This model explicitly restores what others avoid:

  • Truth is a kind—not a construct, not a proposition.
  • It is grounded in the being of God and instantiated fully in Christ: “I am the truth.”
  • Truth confronts, and thus interpretation is never neutral—it is either aligned or suppressive.

This is what sets this framework apart. It does not merely describe how knowing happens—it exposes when knowing becomes fraudulent by denying its own conditions.

I.E. Why It Must Be Foregrounded

This conversation began with the realization that, while your framework rests on this truth, it had not yet been explicitly stated as an axiom. The suppression of truth is the very root of modern confusion—and so the restoration of truth must be the first step in recovery.

It is not enough for this insight to be implied. It must be named, defended, and placed at the front.

I.F. Proposed Axiom for Formal Integration

Axiom 1: Truth is an ontological kind. It is not derived from perception or constructed by reason, but disclosed by being—and most fully instantiated in Christ. Any system that denies truth’s reality commits ontological fraud, and any epistemology that avoids its authority collapses into contradiction. To know truth is to be confronted by it. To deny it is not only false—it is intellectually and morally disintegrative.

I.G. Final Statement

This is not a theological nuance or a philosophical refinement. It is the line. Every system, every worldview, every method of knowing either:

  • Submits to truth as ontological reality,
  • Or simulates coherence on borrowed ground while suppressing its source.

II. Historical Mapping of the Onto–Epistemic Disconnect

Introduction

Having established above that truth is an ontological kind, and that its suppression is both morally evasive and logically fallacious, this second section tracks how that suppression unfolded historically. We map the thinkers and systems that either identified, denied, or deformed the relationship between being and knowing.

This is not a historical survey for its own sake—it is an exposure of philosophical drift, and a demonstration that no system outside of relational ontology has successfully resolved the fracture.

II.A. The Pre-Modern Gestures Toward Ontological Epistemology

Plato Forms: Disembodied Universals Without Covenant

  • Truth resides in the unchanging Forms, accessible only through reason.
  • Gesture: Recognizes a realm of being that grounds knowledge.
  • Failure: The Forms are abstract and disembodied—no personal grounding; no moral accountability.

Plato posited that ultimate reality resides in a realm of immutable, perfect Forms—abstract universals that transcend the material world and give it structure. While this introduced an ontological hierarchy, it was ungrounded in relational or moral reality. These Forms existed independently of creation, covenant, or Creator, rendering “truth” an ideal to be apprehended intellectually, not encountered relationally. Thus, the Platonic model foreshadowed ontology as prior to epistemology but severed it from divine confrontation, moral obligation, or historical self-disclosure. In Scripture’s terms, the Logos is not merely a Form—it is a Person who speaks, convicts, and invites. Plato's ontology lacked this covenantal voice.

Aristotelian Essences: Immanent Structures Without Moral Invitation

  • Knowledge arises from perception, abstracted into universals (form-in-substance).
  • Gesture: Retains teleology and natural kinds.
  • Failure: Epistemology becomes observational and rational, not covenantal or relational.

Aristotle relocated the Forms into the things themselves—asserting that every entity has an essence (its whatness) and a purpose (its telos). This preserved ontological primacy but confined it to immanent categorization rather than transcendent disclosure. His system offered a world ordered by cause, kind, and finality, yet it remained morally inert. There was no divine prerogative to instantiate being, no relational summons to alignment—just a rational taxonomy to be analyzed. Aristotle refined ontology but failed to recover revelation. His model reduced participation in truth to philosophical classification rather than obedient reception of a moral reality.

II.B. The Medieval Synthesis and Its Tensions

Augustine

  • Recognizes truth as unchanging, grounded in God.
  • “We believe in order to know.”
  • Success: Moves toward relational epistemology.
  • Limit: Still partially mediated through Neoplatonism—truth is above the soul but not fully incarnate.

Aquinas’ Scholastic Digression: 

Institutionalizing Ontology Through Essence and Grace, from Submission to Institutional Leverage

  • Synthesizes Aristotelian metaphysics with Christian theology.
  • Introduces analogia entis—being as analogous, not univocal.
  • Gesture: Truth reflects being; God is truth itself.
  • Failure: The model remains hierarchical, not personal-relational; epistemology is filtered through church and scholastic method.

Aquinas systematized Aristotelian metaphysics within a Roman ecclesiastical structure, recasting divine ontology into scholastic categories—essence, act, and infused grace. While affirming the primacy of being, he transformed relational submission into institutional leverage: access to God became mediated not directly through the convicting Spirit or revealed Word, but through sacramental economy, clerical authority, and metaphysical constructs. Ontology was retained, but its relational immediacy was displaced. In place of prophetic confrontation came sacerdotal distribution; in place of covenantal fidelity, ecclesial taxonomy. The truth remained conceptually exalted but was no longer existentially accessible without sanctioned intermediaries.

II.C. The Modern Rupture: The Onto-Epistemic Inversion

Descartes

  • “Cogito, ergo sum” shifts certainty to the self.
  • Truth begins with mental clarity, not external being.
  • Failure: Epistemology becomes self-grounding—ontology is bypassed.

Locke / Hume (Empiricism)

  • Knowledge = sensory impressions.
  • Ontology becomes secondary or denied entirely.
  • Failure: Collapses all being into experience—truth becomes probabilistic or relativized.

Kant’s Onto-Epistemic Rupture: Reason’s Sovereignty Over Revelation

  • Codifies the rupture: we cannot know the noumenon (thing-in-itself).
  • We know only phenomena, shaped by a priori categories of thought.
  • Gesture: Honest admission of the gap.
  • Failure: Formalizes epistemological isolation from being.

Kant's project can be read as a philosophical reaction to this institutional overreach. In seeking to preserve human moral agency from theological absolutism and metaphysical speculation, he severed the link between ontology and cognition. Epistemology, for Kant, was no longer a response to being—it was a filter imposed upon it. His categories of understanding replaced divine self-disclosure with subjective schemata. What had once been relationally encountered as truth was now cognitively domesticated. While Kant intended to safeguard freedom and reason, he inadvertently placed the knowing subject above the known reality—thus completing the rupture that made moral alignment optional and ontological submission nearly unintelligible.

II.D. The Idealist and Phenomenological Reversals

German Idealism (Fichte, Hegel)

  • Reverses the order: spirit or mind produces reality.
  • Truth is a result of dialectical unfolding, not correspondence.
  • Failure: The gap is “resolved” by inversion, not repair.

Heidegger

  • Reintroduces the “question of Being.”
  • Suggests knowing is always within a context of being (Dasein).
  • Gesture: Seeks reconnection.
  • Failure: Impersonal, cryptic, and without revealed referent—no God, no truth-as-person.

II.E. The Collapse and Exploitation  

Analytic Philosophy

  • Shifts focus to logical form, language, and propositions.
  • Treats truth as a property of statements, not a kind.
  • Failure: Bypasses ontology entirely; affirms “truth” without ever asking what it is.

Postmodernism (Derrida, Foucault)

  • Recognizes the disconnect—but concludes that truth is dead, or merely discursive.
  • Truth becomes power, framing, or exclusion.
  • Failure: No referent, no reality, no obligation—only symbolic manipulation.

II.F. Why None of These Restore the Order

Each of the above systems either:

  • Sever the knowing subject from being,
  • Invert the order and claim knowledge creates being,
  • Or dissolve being into function, language, or discourse.

None of them restore:

  • Truth as ontological kind,
  • Epistemology as moral response to revelation,
  • Or Christ as the personal referent and instantiator of being.

II.G. Contrast with the Relational-Ontological Model

II.H. Conclusion

The history of philosophy shows not an unbroken line of insight, but a progressive suppression and evasion of the ontological root of truth. Even the best attempts remain abstract, hierarchical, or impersonal.

The relational-ontological model resolves what they could not—by returning to the only place such a reconciliation is possible: Not in reason, but in revelation. Not in system, but in submission. Not in abstraction, but in the person of Christ, who is truth.

PREVIOUS NEXT