Appendix D1- Addendum to Appendix D

This section continues the evaluation that was commenced in Appendix D. At the heart of every philosophical failure traced in the fault lines is a deeper structural error: the disconnect between ontology and epistemology. Modern systems no longer misunderstand the order—they ignore it. Truth is no longer rooted in being; it is constructed from inference. That inversion is not just a reversal—it is a rupture.

Diagnostic Fault Lines: Applied Analysis of Epistemic Evasions

  • The Gettier Problem– Examines the inadequacy of "justified true belief" models of knowledge. The diagnosis shows that knowledge divorced from ontological alignment results in simulated closure rather than genuine truth alignment.

  • Modal Collapse– Investigates the blurring of possibility and necessity in classical metaphysics and theology. It exposes the loss of moral contingency when modal structures are abstracted from divine relational prerogative.

  • Universals vs. Tropes– Addresses the metaphysical debate over shared properties. It reveals how the denial of God’s right to define ontological types leads to either conceptual inflation (universals) or fragmentation (tropes).

  • Foundationalism vs. Coherentism– Diagnoses two rival models of justification: one that posits self-evident foundations, and one that relies on systemic coherence. Both are shown to simulate epistemic stability while evading typological confrontation.

  • Reliabilism– Critiques the externalist model that defines knowledge by the reliability of belief-forming processes. It exposes the mechanization of truth and the removal of relational and moral accountability.

  • Moral Intuitionism and Constructivism– Analyzes moral frameworks that treat ethical discernment as either innate or socially constructed. It highlights the suppression of moral ontology and the loss of binding typology.

  • Anti-Realism– Explores positions that reject or bracket ontological correspondence, treating truth as linguistic or pragmatic. The analysis shows that anti-realism institutionalizes drift and evades moral confrontation.

  • Tropes of Discursive Displacement– Examines how figurative language (metaphor, irony, etc.) is used to simulate moral and ontological categories without submission to their typological referents. It demonstrates how language becomes a vehicle for epistemic fraud.

    Each is evaluated in turn.

1.1. The Gettier Problem

False Closure in the Absence of Ontological Correspondence

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

In 1963, Edmund Gettier challenged the classical definition of knowledge as justified true belief (JTB). He showed that it is possible to hold a belief that is:

  • Justified,
  • True (by accident),
  • But not connected to the truth in the way knowledge should require.

The canonical examples involve situations where a person believes something for justified but ultimately false reasons, and yet the belief turns out to be true due to coincidence. These examples imply that JTB is insufficient for knowledge.

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

The Gettier framing reflects a narrow onto-epistemic bandwidth in several ways:

  • It treats knowledge as a propositional artefact rather than a relational alignment to reality.
  • It defines justification procedurally (internal coherence, inference) without evaluating typological grounding or moral accountability.
  • It assumes that truth is a static condition of propositions, not the outcome of relational fidelity to disclosed reality.

In short, knowledge is treated as a logical construct rather than a morally tethered act of response to the real.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

The Gettier framing rests on the following epistemic substitution schemes:

  • Coherence Looping The structure assumes knowledge emerges from internal justification mechanisms that are mutually supportive—but unmoored from typology or ontological weight.
  • Computational Substitution Knowing is reduced to processing—justifying, inferring, storing—rather than to a moral act of truth-recognition.
  • Foundational Projection The criteria of “justification” are treated as axiomatic, rather than revealed or accountable to a relational standard.

These templates simulate knowledge without requiring the thinker to stand in proper moral posture before what is true.

4. Why the Problem Persists

The Gettier problem persists because it is never framed as a failure of relational fidelity. The question is reduced to a definitional puzzle:

“What third element should be added to justified true belief to make it ‘real’ knowledge?”

But the problem is not missing a conceptual part—it is missing epistemic submission. It refuses to ask:

  • Who defines justification?
  • What guarantees truth beyond procedural accident?
  • How does the moral alignment of the thinker affect what counts as knowledge?

By suppressing these vertical questions, the model becomes unsolvable by design.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

In the Conical Cognition framework:

  • Knowledge is not defined by structural components, but by relational posture toward ontologically disclosed truth.
  • Justification is not a closed loop—it is a process of recursive disambiguation, morally sharpened by proximity to typological fidelity.
  • Truth is not an accidental match—it is a confrontation that either invites or judges.

Gettier problems disappear when truth is understood as covenantally disclosed rather than accidentally accessed.

In this model, knowledge is fidelity, not formal fit. It is not the overlap between mental content and propositional outcome—it is the alignment of the soul with what God has revealed to be true.

D.1.2. Modal Collapse

Simulated Necessity in the Absence of Moral Contingency

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

Modal collapse refers to the philosophical problem in which all propositions that are true become necessarily true. This undermines the distinction between what could be, must be, and might not have been.

In classical theistic contexts (e.g., Aquinas or Leibniz), modal collapse questions whether divine omniscience or omnipotence renders everything necessary—thereby eliminating genuine contingency, moral agency, or alternative possibility. If God knows (or wills) something eternally, could it truly have been otherwise?

This creates a tension:

  • Either everything is necessary (and freedom is illusory), or
  • God's will is constrained by external contingency (and He is not sovereign).

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

The modal collapse dilemma emerges from a narrow onto-epistemic bandwidth, where:

  • Modality is severed from relational morality and reduced to formal logic or metaphysical determinism.
  • Possibility and necessity are simulated within hypothetical “possible worlds” rather than derived from the covenantal reality of divine discretion.
  • The ADM unit (axiological–deontic–modal) is ignored or replaced by top-down determinism.

The problem is framed in abstraction, without reference to the Creator-creature distinction, moral time, or volitional alignment.

This makes the modal structure appear self-contained—but it is a closed system, lacking typological permission and moral posture.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

Several epistemic substitution schemes converge to generate modal collapse:

  • Modal Simulation Possibility and necessity are reimagined as constructs within formal modal logic systems. This simulates freedom, but only within a predetermined frame.
  • Foundational Projection Modal categories are taken as intrinsic properties of reality rather than expressions of divine prerogative and relational openness.
  • Computational Substitution God's will is treated mechanistically—as if divine foreknowledge auto-generates necessity, reducing freedom to a kind of ontological programming.
  • Phenomenological Suspension In more contemporary responses, the modal challenge is diffused by bracketing questions of divine intention—deferring the issue into “mystery.”

Each of these schemes avoids the real question: What is possibility, and who defines it?

4. Why the Problem Persists

Modal collapse persists because the moral architecture of possibility has been erased.

  • Possibility is not neutral space—it is the expression of what God may instantiate within the bounds of His revealed character.
  • Necessity is not a constraint—it is the ontological result of His immutability and fidelity.
  • Contingency is not random—it is the arena in which moral beings are invited to respond.

By treating these as abstract categories rather than covenantal conditions, modal philosophy manufactures a dilemma that cannot be resolved from within.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

The Conical Cognition framework restores modal clarity by:

  • Grounding possibility, necessity, and contingency in divine relational prerogative (the Double Prerogative of Essence and Instantiation).
  • Defining necessity not as logical entailment, but as relational fidelity—what must be because it flows from God's nature.
  • Reinstating the ADM unit within the creature, where moral agents discern what ought to be done from what can be done in light of divine disclosure.

The cone converges because possibility is not open-ended—it is relationally bounded.

There is no modal collapse in this framework, because modal structure is covenantally ordered, not abstractly deduced. Divine omniscience and human agency co-exist within a system where truth is not exhausted by logic, but shaped by relationship.

D.1.3 Universals vs. Tropes

Typological Ambiguity and the Failure of Ontological Disambiguation

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

The universals vs. tropes debate concerns the nature of shared properties:

  • Do multiple entities instantiate the same universal (e.g., redness), which exists independently and repeatably?
  • Or do they each possess a distinct trope (a particularized property resembling others, but not identical)?

This classic metaphysical controversy spans from Plato and Aristotle to contemporary analytic metaphysics, and touches on key questions:

  • What is the nature of sameness?
  • Are categories abstractly real or conceptually imposed?
  • Can properties be multiply located, or are they tied to particular instances?

Despite centuries of analysis, the debate remains unresolved—fractured between realism, nominalism, conceptualism, and trope theory.

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

This debate arises from narrow onto-epistemic bandwidth, where:

  • Ontological types are severed from divine designation, and treated as either human classifications or metaphysical givens.
  • Typological limits are not seen as covenantal boundaries, but as heuristic groupings (linguistic, perceptual, or structural).
  • No moral or revelatory criteria are permitted to define the reality of a type—resulting in perpetual ambiguity.

The discussion turns on the mechanics of resemblance and instantiation, but never asks: Who has the prerogative to define kind, type, or category?

Without this vertical referent, typology becomes an abstraction game.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

This problem is sustained by several substitution schemes:

  • Linguistic Constructivism “Universals” are treated as by-products of human categorization, rooted in shared language or social cognition.
  • Phenomenological Suspension The actual grounding of the universal is left suspended—concepts are discussed in terms of how they are experienced, not how they are ontologically anchored.
  • Coherence Looping Internal criteria of similarity or resemblance are used to simulate sameness—without external reference to type.
  • Foundational Projection The debate assumes the legitimacy of the category being debated, without asking who has the authority to define it ontologically.

Each strategy maintains a surface-level coherence while evading the need for typological submission to divine prerogative.

4. Why the Problem Persists

The problem persists because it is framed in the absence of divinely established ontological kinds.

  • “Redness” is not a conceptual abstraction—it is a created category that reflects the structuring of being under God’s design.
  • “Human nature,” “justice,” or “beauty” are not linguistic consensus—they are types, embedded in creation by fiat.
  • By refusing to anchor types in divine will and delimitation, the debate cannot resolve what counts as real sameness.

The question being asked—what makes two things one in kind—cannot be answered if kinds themselves are ungrounded.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

The Conical Cognition model resolves this debate by rooting typology in anaphatic limits and divine prerogative:

  • Every ontological type has a God-defined range—an extensive vibration that delimits what may rightly instantiate it.
  • Shared properties (universals) are real because they correspond to ontological types, not because they resemble or cluster.
  • Tropes may describe particular manifestations, but these are downstream of divine taxonomy, not alternatives to it.

Types are not abstractions—they are covenantal categories.

Recursive disambiguation allows the thinker to discern what rightly belongs to a type, by testing resemblance against revealed ontic integrity. The epistemic cone narrows not by comparing traits, but by submitting to reality as named and structured by the Creator.

D.1.4 Foundationalism vs. Coherentism

Duelling Substitutions within a Suppressed Ontological Frame

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

This epistemological controversy centers on how beliefs are justified:

  • Foundationalists argue that some beliefs are basic—justified independently—and all others must be built upon them.
  • Coherentists argue that no belief is basic; justification arises from how well beliefs support and cohere with each other.

The question is: What makes a belief justified? Must there be a foundational stopping point, or is justification systemic and circular?

While both models attempt to explain rational belief formation, neither offers a universally satisfying account. Instead, the debate has generated centuries of counterexamples, regress problems, and theoretical restatements without convergence.

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

This entire debate is conducted within a narrow onto-epistemic bandwidth. It assumes:

  • Justification is an internal structure, not a relational posture toward disclosed reality.
  • Beliefs are primarily cognitive artifacts, not moral responses to confrontation.
  • Truth is inferentially approached, not personally revealed.

As a result, the debate is structured around the location of epistemic confidence, not the ontology of what is believed, nor the alignment of the knower with the source of truth.

The model asks: “How do I know that I know?” without first asking: “Have I submitted to what is true?”

This is bandwidth suppression disguised as methodological rigor.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

This conflict reflects dueling epistemic substitution schemes:

  • Foundationalists rely on Foundational Projection: They posit “self-evident,” “properly basic,” or “incorrigible” beliefs—without disclosing the ontological grounding or moral trust required for such claims.
  • Coherentists lean heavily on Coherence Looping: Justification is simulated by interdependence—truth becomes a function of networked affirmation, not correspondence.

Both sides substitute internal structures for relational access to the real.

Justification becomes a mirror held up to the system, rather than an orientation toward something that exists independently of the system.

4. Why the Problem Persists

The debate cannot be resolved because it suppresses the ontological and moral structure of knowing:

  • It treats beliefs as atomic units or semantic links, not as covenantal responses to divine confrontation.
  • It does not allow for typological testing of what is believed—only architectural evaluation of how beliefs connect.
  • It assumes the goal of epistemology is internal stability, not external alignment with revealed truth.

In this framework, justification is always incomplete, because the epistemic cone is never permitted to converge.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

The Conical Cognition model reframes the issue:

  • Justification is not architectural—it is relational. It arises when a belief is formed in submission to truth that confronts the thinker through typological, moral, and ontological alignment.
  • The belief structure is recursively tested, not for coherence or foundationality, but for fidelity—does it point to the apex?
  • Thought narrows through recursive disambiguation—not to arrive at a “basic belief” or “web coherence,” but to reach the place where truth exposes and realigns.

Foundationalism simulates authority. Coherentism simulates integrity. Only relational ontology grants either one moral substance.

In this model, a belief is justified not because it rests on something prior, nor because it harmonizes with its neighbors, but because it is yielded to what God has revealed to be real.

D.1.5 Reliabilism

Functional Consistency as a Surrogate for Relational Fidelity

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

Reliabilism is a family of theories in epistemology which asserts that a belief is justified (or counts as knowledge) if it is produced by a reliable cognitive process—one that tends to yield true beliefs.

This shifts the focus from internal states (e.g., evidence, justification) to external process integrity:

  • If a process reliably tracks truth (like perception, memory, or testimony), then the beliefs it produces can be called knowledge—even if the agent lacks access to how or why they are justified.

This resolves some internalist regress problems, but introduces new issues:

  • Is reliability enough without awareness or intentionality?
  • What counts as a reliable process—and who decides?
  • Can a belief be reliably produced yet still not be truthfully aligned?

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

Reliabilism, like other naturalized epistemologies, operates within a narrow onto-epistemic bandwidth by:

  • Treating belief formation as mechanical output, not moral posture.
  • Defining “success” as predictive correlation rather than covenantal alignment.
  • Assuming that truth-tracking can be evaluated independently of typology, ontology, or divine disclosure.

In essence, reliabilism replaces truth as encounter with truth as function. It asks whether the machine works—not whether the person is rightly aligned.

This is epistemic efficiency without epistemic accountability.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

Reliabilism primarily relies on the following epistemic substitution schemes:

  • Computational Substitution The act of knowing is recast as a process: reliable input → output. This simulates fidelity with function.
  • Foundational Projection The idea of “reliable processes” is taken as self-evident—yet their validity is never examined against typological or moral standards.
  • Affective Calibration (in some variants) Testimonial or social reliabilism introduces group-dependence and affective resonance as surrogate validators, further narrowing access to ontological fidelity.

Reliability is made the proxy for relational integrity—but without any relational test.

4. Why the Problem Persists

Reliabilism fails because it treats truth as performance, not presence.

  • It never asks whether the process itself is rightly oriented toward God’s disclosed reality.
  • It assumes that truth is a pattern to be tracked, not a confrontation to be answered.
  • It cannot distinguish between mechanically valid reasoning and morally misaligned justification (e.g., propaganda that is persuasive but not true).

Moreover, it cannot account for epistemic regeneration—how fallen cognitive processes are restored. It lacks a theology of mind.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

In the Conical Cognition model:

  • Reliability is not dismissed—but it is subordinated to typological and moral fidelity.
  • A process is “reliable” not because it performs well statistically, but because it moves toward the apex—toward truth as disclosed and typologically bounded.
  • The true test of knowledge is not whether it works often, but whether it is ontologically aligned and relationally faithful.

What matters is not just whether the mind tracks truth, but whether the soul submits to it.

Reliabilism asks: Is the belief well-formed? Conical Cognition asks: Is the thinker rightly postured toward what God has made known?

Only the latter can ground a system of knowledge that is accountable, covenantal, and redemptively coherent.

D.1.6 Moral Intuitionism and Constructivism

Affective Plausibility in the Absence of Ontological Authority

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

Moral intuitionism and constructivism attempt to explain how moral knowledge or moral obligation arises without appealing to divine command, natural law, or metaphysical realism.

  • Intuitionism posits that we know what is right through immediate moral perception or “seeming.”
  • Constructivism holds that moral truths are not discovered but constructed—either by individual reflection (Kantian versions) or social consensus (Rawlsian versions).

Both frameworks try to secure morality without anchoring it in an external, ontological source. Instead, they rely on intersubjective plausibility and felt immediacy.

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

These models operate within a narrow onto-epistemic bandwidth because they:

  • Refuse to ground moral obligation in typological reality or divine fiat.
  • Sever moral discernment from covenantal context—there is no apex to submit to.
  • Treat conscience as an affective instrument or rational construct, not a relational organ of response.

Moral intuition becomes either a psychological reflex or a social adaptation—not an act of ontological recognition.

This suppression makes true moral knowledge epistemically unstable and morally weightless.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

These models rely on the following epistemic substitution schemes:

  • Affective Calibration Moral truth is reduced to what “feels right” or seems intuitive—calibrated to evolved sensitivities or social conditioning.
  • Coherence Looping Social constructivism defines moral truth by agreement or functional integration within communities, producing ethical echo chambers.
  • Phenomenological Suspension Any reference to an ontological source (e.g., God, eternal law) is bracketed as speculative or unknowable—leaving morality as lived experience, not objective reality.
  • Foundational Projection Constructs like fairness, dignity, or autonomy are treated as moral primitives without metaphysical grounding—smuggled in under rhetorical neutrality.

4. Why the Problem Persists

These systems cannot resolve the moral problem because they refuse to define goodness ontologically.

  • Intuitions are not self-validating.
  • Social agreement does not equal moral rightness.
  • Constructed norms carry no transcendent authority.

Moreover, both models collapse under pluralism:

  • Competing intuitions cannot be adjudicated.
  • Social constructs can justify both justice and atrocity.

Moral reasoning without ontological submission becomes a simulation of virtue, not its discovery.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

The Conical Cognition model restores moral knowledge to its rightful place by:

  • Grounding morality in the ontological character of God, not evolving instincts or communal negotiation.
  • Viewing conscience as a relational instrument—responsive to truth, not autonomous from it.
  • Anchoring obligation in the deontic axis of the ADM unit, nested within typological and axiological structures.

Moral knowledge is gained not by looking inward, nor by voting outward, but by ascending the cone toward revealed righteousness.

Moral clarity is not a feeling. It is a function of relational nearness to the apex.

In this view, intuition may play a role, but it must be tested against:

  • Typological fidelity,
  • Scriptural revelation,
  • The revealed will of the God who defines what is good.

Only then does moral discernment regain its epistemic gravity and ethical integrity.

D.1.7 Anti-Realism

Semantic Agnosticism as Ontological Abdication

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

Anti-realism is the position that truth, meaning, or reality is not mind-independent. What we call “truth” or “fact” is either:

  • Dependent on language, interpretation, or social context (semantic or cultural anti-realism),
  • Or simply undecidable, because reality-in-itself is inaccessible (epistemic anti-realism).

Anti-realists often assert:

  • “There is no fact of the matter apart from interpretation.”
  • “Truth is what works in a given context.”
  • “Meaning is constructed by use, not correspondence.”

The result is a world where meaning floats, truth shifts, and reality cannot bind. This appears humble or sophisticated, but it is epistemically fatal.

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

Anti-realism represents one of the most severe forms of onto-epistemic bandwidth suppression. It:

  • Denies vertical correspondence: There is no ontological referent beyond discourse.
  • Blocks typological access: Categories are linguistic tools, not real distinctions.
  • Suspends moral accountability: No truth confronts—only meanings circulate.

The anti-realist denies that the apex exists at all—and therefore insists that all narrowing is either coercion or illusion.

Thought becomes an open circuit—endlessly referential, but never converging.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

Anti-realism thrives on a blend of epistemic substitution schemes:

  • Linguistic Constructivism All meaning is defined within language-games; referents are never ontologically anchored.
  • Phenomenological Suspension Ontology is bracketed—only perception, intention, or use matters. Reality becomes interpretive horizon, not referential standard.
  • Coherence Looping Truth is judged by internal integration or intersubjective acceptance—not external reality.
  • Affective Calibration What “resonates” is preserved; what confronts is destabilized and often deconstructed.

These schemes together constitute a closed symbolic economy: all terms are traded, but none are backed by ontological currency.

4. Why the Problem Persists

Anti-realism cannot resolve the problem of meaning because it refuses to let meaning be anchored.

  • It cannot distinguish between true reference and plausible function.
  • It cannot explain moral obligation, typological fidelity, or divine speech.
  • It collapses under its own denial: if nothing corresponds, even anti-realism is unmoored.

It is not that anti-realism lacks sophistication—it lacks permission. It refuses to acknowledge the moral accountability of thought.

By eliminating the apex, anti-realism ensures that no cone can ever form. All thought becomes semiotic vapor.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

The Conical Cognition model dismantles anti-realism by restoring:

  • Truth as ontological category, not interpretive construct.
  • Meaning as referential fidelity, not symbolic circulation.
  • Speech as covenantal gesture, not self-reinforcing code.

In this model:

  • Words point because reality is structured by the Creator who speaks.
  • Concepts narrow because they are meant to correspond to types, not merely play roles.
  • Truth confronts because it is revealed, not derived.

The epistemic cone exists because reality does. Meaning converges because types constrain it. And truth binds because God speaks.

In this light, anti-realism is not a bold admission of finitude—it is a willful refusal to ascend. And that refusal leads not to humility, but to semantic exile.

D.1.8 Tropes of Discursive Displacement

Symbolic Drift as Semiotic Evasion of Typological Confrontation

1. The Problem as Commonly Framed

In critical discourse theory and modern semiotics, tropes—figures of speech like metaphor, irony, metonymy, and synecdoche—are understood not merely as rhetorical flourishes but as mechanisms of meaning-making. In post-structural contexts, they become tools by which language shifts, evolves, or undermines its own claims to stability.

While this fluidity is often celebrated as subversive or creative, it presents a deeper problem:

Can tropes simulate truth without ever submitting to it?

When figures become functions, and substitutions stand in for referents, discourse can displace meaning—keeping form while removing moral or ontological accountability.

2. The Bandwidth Suppression

Tropic substitution operates within a narrowed bandwidth when:

  • Tropes are used to evoke types without submitting to them. (e.g., calling something “grace” that has no ontological referent in divine reality.)
  • Discursive meaning becomes free-floating—anchored not in being, but in effect or affect.
  • Semantic drift is allowed to occur without typological correction—so that metaphor becomes simulacrum.

Language loses its covenantal integrity when signs no longer bind to what they signify.

Tropes become tools of discursive evasion, enabling moral and ontological displacement under the guise of symbolic plausibility.

3. The Substitution Scheme(s) Used

Discursive displacement through tropes manifests multiple substitution schemes:

  • Linguistic Constructivism Words are treated as instruments of social construction, not conveyors of reality. Tropes bend meaning toward utility.
  • Phenomenological Suspension What matters is not what the sign points to, but how it is encountered or interpreted. Tropes become affective events.
  • Affective Calibration Terms gain traction by how well they resonate, not how accurately they align. This enables semantic laundering of ontological concepts.
  • Typological Simulation A newly relevant term: tropes are used to mimic typological language—offering the feel of theological or moral weight without ontic referent.

4. Why the Problem Persists

Tropes displace meaning when their referential load is no longer tested against the apex.

  • Without ontological submission, metaphor becomes manipulation.
  • Without typological integrity, synecdoche becomes distortion.
  • Without reverence, irony becomes corrosion.

In this context, the trope is not a bridge to truth but a mask for evasion. Words retain form but lose gravity.

The result is semiotic simulation: signs that circle within discursive frameworks while concealing typological rebellion.

5. Resolution via Conical Cognition

The Conical Cognition model restores tropes to their rightful place:

  • As tools of reverent reference, not discursive detachment.
  • As modes of approach, not mechanisms of evasion.
  • As analogical gestures, not ontological substitutions.

Tropes work only when tethered—to types, to revealed truth, to the Creator whose speech is binding.

A metaphor that does not ascend is a mask. A synecdoche that does not submit is a counterfeit. Language becomes faithful only when it bends upward.

In this view, the problem of discursive displacement is not semiotic—it is moral. It is a refusal to let meaning be shaped by truth, and a refusal to let words bear the weight of what they claim to signify.

Diagnostic Summary

Tropes become fraudulent when:

  • Their referents are typologically undefined,
  • Their function is persuasive rather than revelatory,
  • Their use mimics truth rather than submitting to it.

Faithful language discloses. Fraudulent language drifts. The difference is not rhetorical technique—but epistemic posture.

D.1.9. Epistemic Evasion and the Conical Reckoning

Each of these controversies arises within a self-enclosed epistemic system; avoids ascent toward a grounding ontological source; and persists by deploying a now-familiar set of epistemic substitution schemes:

  • Coherence looping (“It fits with my other ideas”)
  • Foundational projection (“This seems obvious to me, so it must be true”)
  • Modal simulation (“I can imagine it, so it’s real enough”)
  • Linguistic constructivism (“If I say it clearly, it becomes true”)
  • Affective calibration (“It feels right, so it probably is”)
  • Computational substitution (“The model works, so the reality doesn’t matter”)
  • Phenomenological suspension (“Let’s just bracket the real world and talk about experience”)

These patterns are not incidental—they are the default operating modes of autonomous reason. And across every case, one deeper theme has now become unmistakable:

Ontology is simultaneously presumed and denied.

These frameworks require fixed referents to make their objections intelligible, yet they deny ontological access when it comes to grounding truth.They borrow stability while arguing for indeterminacy.They lean on the real while asserting that nothing can be known as it is.

This is not merely error. It is structured evasion—a refusal to acknowledge what these very systems cannot function without.

D.1.9.i. The Implication for Honest Thinkers

No one controversy makes the pattern obvious. But when taken together, the implications become unavoidable:

  • The errors are not accidental—they are structural.

  • The questions do not remain unresolved because they are too difficult, but because they are being asked from a posture that cannot permit resolution.

We are not merely observing flawed ideas—we are witnessing a shared architecture of evasion.  And this is precisely why a new framework is needed. Not one more theory within the system, but a higher structure——one that reorders the relation between being, knowing, and meaning.—one that rescues thought from recursion and returns it to reality.

The next section introduces that framework. It is called the Conical Cognition Model .

PREVIOUS NEXT